International Management: a case of BASF GERMANY ESTABLISHING PLANT IN SOUTH CAROLINA
https://ilokabenneth.blogspot.com/2014/09/international-management-case-of-basf.html
Author: Iloka Benneth Chiemelie
Published: 22-September-2014
1. Introduction
Business ethics is no longer a new topic of
discussion in modern day business because it has been argued and debated by
both researchers and business practitioners. Ethics in the business sense
entails doing things in the right way, where right way is defined as a way in
which the outcome is beneficial to the majority of the public (stakeholders). However,
since the focus is on majority of the public, the question is whether
neglecting the minority of the public in actuality is ethical. Thus, it creates
a new realm of understanding which is focused on testing new ways that both the
majority and minority can be catered for in the outcome of an ethical decision.
As such, a number of theories have been developed in line with such
understanding and such theories include The Discourse Ethics and Deontological
Theories of Ethics.
The purpose of this paper is to apply both
discourse and deontological ethics in the decision process of BASF – a German
company- to open a new plant in Beaufort County, in the mist of providing the
local communities with jobs and potentially poisoning the local tourist
heritage. This research is basically divided into three, the first is the
introduction which highlights what is to be done and how it will be done. The
second is a review of literature, while the final section is a conclusion and
recommendation on decision process for BASF.
1.1. Discussing
deontology and discourse ethics: advantages and disadvantages
Majority of the theoretical discussions done
on ethics in line with communication have focused more on studies that view
deontological principles as governing professional communication practices (Churchill,
1983; Donaldson, 1985, 1999). In any case, if the importance of codes that
drive the action and interactions of professionals are not disregarded, it
becomes clear that communication ethics is also of great concern in terms of
the way that its intersubjective relationships are constructed. Communication
ethics brings to life the tensions existing among determinants that define the
intersubjective contacts and constantly reform the meaning, frames, and forms
of language that are used to define both its contexts and interlocution. The
way subjects try to associate their own freedom action and personal interest in
order to respect the identities and interests of other people is also related
to the ethical framework (Donnelly, 2003).
In the communication context, ethics
associated with current communication process should bear the following in
mind: a) the modes that information are presented in the media, b) the way such
presented information are disseminated and critical approaches, c) the
intersubjective values that attempt to expose the views of each social actor
that is involves in the communication action, and linking or not linking the
social actor to other people; d) the communicative situation and relational
contexts that are established when the subjects activate common language views
with the intention of establishing mutual understanding, and e) personal
interests that are used to guide not just the strategic actions that are viewed
as contrasting with common goods, but also those that direct the discursive
engagement between actors and their peer; which makes it necessary to view it
as a central element of a communication interaction.
Apart from the above views, it is important
to mention that ethics in the sense of communication is intended to evaluate
the role that interest and language play in practical relationship existing
between the subject and the approaches he/she should adopt in conditions under
which the event is happening, through a form of discursive interaction in the
public cope, in order to ensure that individuals reach an understanding on
their personal interests and needs.
In The
Theory of Communication Action (1987), Habermas attempted to a discourse
ethics in order to show language use can be adopted in promoting mutual
understanding and provisional agreement between people participating in
practical discussion with a collective view on the assessment of common issues
and private interest. For Habermas, ethics is an established link with personal
horizon of interest, values, global views, and choices, but the moral view
point adopted by participants in a discussion is used to make reference to the enlargement
of the subject horizon in order to build the right room for conflict resolution
and collective problem solving.
1.2. Theory
of Discourse ethics
Habermas’s (1987) presented an outline of
discourse ethics as a way of establishing moral deliberation as established in
his Principle of Universalization, which is based on the idea that all parties
affected by utterance can accept those consequences. Leeper (1996) viewed
discourse ethics as an alternative to relativism in situational views of public
relation. In his discussion which was based on earlier establishments by
Habernas, he presented ideal speech situation and how claim of validity can be
used to generates ethical codes for public relations practitioners. In
conclusion, he made known that his works can be used evaluate and guide public
relations views. In any case, it is important to understand that although
providing an excellent background on the outcomes of discourse ethics, the work
done by Leeper didn’t not address the procedural implications of the Habermas
principles in full.
Meisenbach (2006) highlighted the advantage
of the advantages of discourse ethics as being based on the principles
established by Habermas, which are:
1.
It
helps to identify an utterance for deliberation,
2.
It
identifies all the subjects that will be affected by via implementation of such
utterance,
3.
It
helps to articulate utterance to all the affected subjects as identified,
4.
It
debates the affected parties, consequences, and values of the utterance in a
discursive way, and
5.
It
helps to form judgment of validity and acceptability of the proposed utterance.
In essence, discourse ethics is centered on
creating a common argument grounds that has the views, and desires of all
subjects combine in the argument process, and establish an equal consensus that
is mutually beneficial to all subjects. However, it has the disadvantage of not
necessary representing the view of all affected subjects especially when the
subjects are in large volume and employ only few people to represent their own
grouped opinion.
1.3. Theory
of deontology
Numerous philosophers have dropped the whole
view of teleological agenda based on the argument that moral goodness is not
related with generating pleasure, consequences, and/or happiness. In real
definition, deontological theories are duty-based. This implies that according
to deontologist, morality is all about fulfilling moral obligations or duties.
However, duties in the deontological views are not always about giving absolute
obedience to moral rules. Thus, it is required of subjects to do (or no to do)
certain things in order to ensure that they uphold the rule of law. The extent
that a given moral rule can be described as being right or wrong is determined
by how independent its consequences are or by level of happiness or pleasure
acquired by abiding or not abiding with that moral rule.
Thus, the advantage of deontlogy is that it
creates the right moral ethics for understanding whether something is right
(done in accordance with moral rule) or wrong (not done in accordance with
moral rule). However, it has the disadvantage of a subject potentially creating
pain for himself in order to create pleasure for another subject.
1.4. Decision
for BASF based on the above theories
With the two theories already discussed, the
decision process will be based on application of the two theories as:
1.5.Decision based on discourse ethics
The company should open the chemical plant in
Beaufort Count, South Carolina. This is because the residents of the community
as well as the South Carolinian government has welcomed BASF and they are
willing to work with them in order to see the company successful in the region
and create jobs for locals in the process. Thus, since discourse ethics entails
discussing with involved stakeholders and coming out with decisions that are
mutually beneficial to all stakeholders, it becomes clear that the decision to
go ahead with building production plant in this area is right for BASF as they
have been welcomed by both the government and residents, and they have needed
raw materials available in this location.
1.6.Decision based on deontological view
The company should note go ahead with opening
the production plant in Beaufort County. This is because deontological view is
of the notion that decisions should be made in accordance with moral rules.
Since there is an already established tourist heritage (Hilton Head), opening a
company that will pollute the air and water and destroy this cultural tourist
heritage is against more rule. Thus, if the company is to be deontological
ethical, it should not open the production plant in Beaufort County.
1.7. Conclusion
and recommendation
This research has shown that the presence of
numerous ethical theories and frameworks is further complicating ethical
practices, as different theories have different views (Doyle, 2010a, 2010b;
Easley, 2004; Elfstorm, 2000). For instance, deontological ethics is against
BASF opening the chemical plant in Beaufort Count because it is against moral
rules, while discourse ethics is in support of opening the chemical plan in the
same location because it is what the people want.
However, this research recommends that in
order to b ethical, BASF should focus on what the people want and not the moral
rules as it is the same people that created the moral rules and they can decide
to change it for a greater course. Thus, it is conclude that BASF should go
ahead with opening the production plant.
References
Boatright, J. R. (2000). „Globalisation and the
ethics of business‟. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10 (1): 1-6.
Bondy, K., Matten, D. and Moon, J. (2004). „The
adoption of voluntary codes of conduct in MNCs: a three-country comparative
study‟. Business and Society Review, 109 (4): 449-477.
Carr, A. Z. (1968). „Is business bluffing ethical?‟.
Harvard Business Review, January.
Carroll,
A. B. (1987). „In search of the moral manager‟. Business Horizons, 30 (2):
7-15.
Churchill, Robert
P. (1983). “Nuclear Arms as a Philosophical and Moral Issue.” Annals of the
American Academy of Political and Social Science 469 (September):46–57.
Ciulla, J. B., Martin, C. and Solomon, R.C. (2007).
Honest Work: A Business Ethics Reader. Oxford University Press.
Cordeiro, W. P. (2003). „Should business ethics be
different in transitional economies?‟. Journal of Business Ethics, Part 1, 47
(4): 327-35.
De George, R. T. (1999). Business Ethics. Upper Saddle,
River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Donaldson, Thomas.
(1985). “Nuclear Deterrence and Self Defense.” Ethics95 (3, April): 537–48.
Donaldson, Thomas.
(1999). “Moral Minimums for Multinationals.” In Ethics and International
Affairs: A Reader, ed. Joel H. Rosenthal. Washington D.C.: Georgetown
University Press.
Donnelly, Jack.
(2003). Human Rights in Theory and Practice. 2nd ed. Ithaca NY: Cornell
University Press.
Doyle, Thomas E.
(2010a). “Moral Dilemmas: Acquiring Nuclear Weapons in the Second Nuclear Age.”
Unpublished doctoral dissertation. University of California, Irvine.
Doyle, Thomas E.
(2010b). “Reviving Nuclear Ethics: A Renewed Research Agenda for the
Twenty-First Century.” Ethics and International Affairs 24(3, Fall): 287–308.
Duska, R. (2000). „Business ethics: oxymoron or good
business?‟. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10 (1): 111-129.
Easley, Eric S.
(2004). The War Over Perpetual Peace: An Exploration Into the History of a
Foundational International Relations Text. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
Elfstrom, Gerard.
(2000). “The Ethical Responsibilities of Multinational Corporations: TheCase of
North American Aluminum Companies in Jamaica.” In Ethics in International Affairs,
ed. Andrew Valls. Lanham MD: Rowman & LittlefieldPublishers, Inc.
Fisher, C. and Lovell, A. (2003). Business Ethics
and Values. Harlow, N.Y: FT Prentice Hall.
Friedman, M. (1970). „The Social Responsibility of
Business is to Increase Its Profits‟. In Beauchamp, T. and Bowie, N. (ed.)
(1988), Ethical Theory and Business, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall.
Goodpaster, K. (2007). Conscience and Corporate
Culture. UK: Blackwell Publishing.
HABERMAS, Jürgen
(1987). The Theory of communicative action: vol.II Lifeworld and system: a
critique of functionalism reason. Boston: Beacon, Press.
Levis, J. (2006). „Adoption of corporate social
responsibility codes by multinational companies‟. Journal of Asia Economics, 17
(1): 50-55.
Maclagan, P. (1998). Management and Morality.
London: Sage Publications.
O‟Higgins, E. (2003). „Part 2: global business means
global responsibilities: research: global strategies - contradictions and
consequences‟. Corporate Governance: The International Journal of Effective
Board Performance, 3 (3): 52-66.
Rest, J. R. and Narváez, D. (1994). Moral
Development in the Professions: Psychology and Applied Ethics. Taylor &
Francis.
Treviño, L. K. and Brown, M. E. (2004). „Managing to
be ethical: debunking five business ethics myths‟. Academy of Management
Executive, 18 (2): 69-81.
Verstraeten, J. (1998). „From business ethics to the
vocation of business leaders to humanize the world of business‟. Business
Ethics: A European Review, 7 (2): 111-124.
Werhane, P. H. and Freeman, R. E. (1999). „Business
ethics: The state of the art‟. International Journal of Management Reviews, 1
(1): 1-16.
Windsor, D. (2004). „The development of
international business norms‟. Business Ethics Quarterly, 14 (4): 729-754.